Total order
In mathematics, a linear order, total order, simple order, or (non-strict) ordering is a binary relation on some set X, which is transitive, antisymmetric, and total (this relation is denoted here by infix ≤). A set paired with a total order is called a totally ordered set, a linearly ordered set, a simply ordered set, or a chain.
If X is totally ordered under ≤, then the following statements hold for all a, b and c in X:
- If a ≤ b and b ≤ a then a = b (antisymmetry);
- If a ≤ b and b ≤ c then a ≤ c (transitivity);
- a ≤ b or b ≤ a (totality).
Antisymmetry eliminates uncertain cases when both a precedes b and b precedes a.[1] A relation having the property of "totality" means that any pair of elements in the set of the relation are comparable under the relation. This also means that the set can be diagrammed as a line of elements, giving it the name linear.[2] Totality also implies reflexivity, i.e., a ≤ a. Therefore, a total order is also a partial order. The partial order has a weaker form of the third condition. (It requires only reflexivity, not totality.) An extension of a given partial order to a total order is called a linear extension of that partial order.
Contents
Strict total order
For each (non-strict) total order ≤ there is an associated asymmetric (hence irreflexive) relation <, called a strict total order, which can equivalently be defined in two ways:
- a < b if and only if a ≤ b and a ≠ b
- a < b if and only if not b ≤ a (i.e., < is the inverse of the complement of ≤)
Properties:
- The relation is transitive: a < b and b < c implies a < c.
- The relation is trichotomous: exactly one of a < b, b < a and a = b is true.
- The relation is a strict weak order, where the associated equivalence is equality.
We can work the other way and start by choosing < as a transitive trichotomous binary relation; then a total order ≤ can equivalently be defined in two ways:
- a ≤ b if and only if a < b or a = b
- a ≤ b if and only if not b < a
Two more associated orders are the complements ≥ and >, completing the quadruple {<, >, ≤, ≥}.
We can define or explain the way a set is totally ordered by any of these four relations; the notation implies whether we are talking about the non-strict or the strict total order.
Examples
- The letters of the alphabet ordered by the standard dictionary order, e.g., A < B < C etc.
- Any subset of a totally ordered set, with the restriction of the order on the whole set.
- Any set of cardinal numbers or ordinal numbers (more strongly, these are well-orders).
- If X is any set and f an injective function from X to a totally ordered set then f induces a total ordering on X by setting x1 < x2 if and only if f(x1) < f(x2).
- The lexicographical order on the Cartesian product of a set of totally ordered sets indexed by an ordinal, is itself a total order. For example, any set of words ordered alphabetically is a totally ordered set, viewed as a subset of a Cartesian product of a countable number of copies of a set formed by adding the space symbol to the alphabet (and defining a space to be less than any letter).
- The set of real numbers ordered by the usual less than (<) or greater than (>) relations is totally ordered, hence also the subsets of natural numbers, integers, and rational numbers. Each of these can be shown to be the unique (to within isomorphism) smallest example of a totally ordered set with a certain property, (a total order A is the smallest with a certain property if whenever B has the property, there is an order isomorphism from A to a subset of B):
- The natural numbers comprise the smallest totally ordered set with no upper bound.
- The integers comprise the smallest totally ordered set with neither an upper nor a lower bound.
- The rational numbers comprise the smallest totally ordered set which is dense in the real numbers. The definition of density used here says that for every 'a' and 'b' in the real numbers such that 'a' < 'b', there is a 'q' in the rational numbers such that 'a' < 'q' < 'b'.
- The real numbers comprise the smallest unbounded totally ordered set that is connected in the order topology (defined below).
- Ordered fields are totally ordered by definition. They include the rational numbers and the real numbers.
Further concepts
Chains
While chain is sometimes merely a synonym for totally ordered set, it can also refer to a totally ordered subset of some partially ordered set. The latter definition has a crucial role in Zorn's lemma. The height of a poset denotes the cardinality of its largest chain in this sense.
For example, consider the set of all subsets of the integers partially ordered by inclusion. Then the set { In : n is a natural number}, where In is the set of natural numbers below n, is a chain in this ordering, as it is totally ordered under inclusion: If n≤k, then In is a subset of Ik.
Lattice theory
One may define a totally ordered set as a particular kind of lattice, namely one in which we have
- for all a, b.
We then write a ≤ b if and only if . Hence a totally ordered set is a distributive lattice.
Finite total orders
A simple counting argument will verify that any non-empty finite totally ordered set (and hence any non-empty subset thereof) has a least element. Thus every finite total order is in fact a well order. Either by direct proof or by observing that every well order is order isomorphic to an ordinal one may show that every finite total order is order isomorphic to an initial segment of the natural numbers ordered by <. In other words, a total order on a set with k elements induces a bijection with the first k natural numbers. Hence it is common to index finite total orders or well orders with order type ω by natural numbers in a fashion which respects the ordering (either starting with zero or with one).
Category theory
Totally ordered sets form a full subcategory of the category of partially ordered sets, with the morphisms being maps which respect the orders, i.e. maps f such that if a ≤ b then f(a) ≤ f(b).
A bijective map between two totally ordered sets that respects the two orders is an isomorphism in this category.
Order topology
For any totally ordered set X we can define the open intervals (a, b) = {x : a < x and x < b}, (−∞, b) = {x : x < b}, (a, ∞) = {x : a < x} and (−∞, ∞) = X. We can use these open intervals to define a topology on any ordered set, the order topology.
When more than one order is being used on a set one talks about the order topology induced by a particular order. For instance if N is the natural numbers, < is less than and > greater than we might refer to the order topology on N induced by < and the order topology on N induced by > (in this case they happen to be identical but will not in general).
The order topology induced by a total order may be shown to be hereditarily normal.
Completeness
A totally ordered set is said to be complete if every nonempty subset that has an upper bound, has a least upper bound. For example, the set of real numbers R is complete but the set of rational numbers Q is not.
There are a number of results relating properties of the order topology to the completeness of X:
- If the order topology on X is connected, X is complete.
- X is connected under the order topology if and only if it is complete and there is no gap in X (a gap is two points a and b in X with a < b such that no c satisfies a < c < b.)
- X is complete if and only if every bounded set that is closed in the order topology is compact.
A totally ordered set (with its order topology) which is a complete lattice is compact. Examples are the closed intervals of real numbers, e.g. the unit interval [0,1], and the affinely extended real number system (extended real number line). There are order-preserving homeomorphisms between these examples.
Sums of orders
For any two disjoint total orders and , there is a natural order on the set , which is called the sum of the two orders or sometimes just :
- For , holds if and only if one of the following holds:
- and
- and
- and
Intutitively, this means that the elements of the second set are added on top of the elements of the first set.
More generally, if is a totally ordered index set, and for each the structure is a linear order, where the sets are pairwise disjoint, then the natural total order on is defined by
- For , holds if:
- Either there is some with
- or there are some in with ,
Orders on the Cartesian product of totally ordered sets
In order of increasing strength, i.e., decreasing sets of pairs, three of the possible orders on the Cartesian product of two totally ordered sets are:
- Lexicographical order: (a,b) ≤ (c,d) if and only if a < c or (a = c and b ≤ d). This is a total order.
- (a,b) ≤ (c,d) if and only if a ≤ c and b ≤ d (the product order). This is a partial order.
- (a,b) ≤ (c,d) if and only if (a < c and b < d) or (a = c and b = d) (the reflexive closure of the direct product of the corresponding strict total orders). This is also a partial order.
All three can similarly be defined for the Cartesian product of more than two sets.
Applied to the vector space Rn, each of these make it an ordered vector space.
See also examples of partially ordered sets.
A real function of n real variables defined on a subset of Rn defines a strict weak order and a corresponding total preorder on that subset.
Related structures
A binary relation that is antisymmetric, transitive, and reflexive (but not necessarily total) is a partial order.
A group with a compatible total order is a totally ordered group.
There are only a few nontrivial structures that are (interdefinable as) reducts of a total order. Forgetting the orientation results in a betweenness relation. Forgetting the location of the ends results in a cyclic order. Forgetting both data results in a separation relation.[3]
See also
- Order theory
- Well-order
- Suslin's problem
- Countryman line
- Prefix order – a downward total partial order
Notes
References
- George Grätzer (1971). Lattice theory: first concepts and distributive lattices. W. H. Freeman and Co. ISBN 0-7167-0442-0
- John G. Hocking and Gail S. Young (1961). Topology. Corrected reprint, Dover, 1988. ISBN 0-486-65676-4de:Lineare Ordnung