Convex preferences

From Infogalactic: the planetary knowledge core
Jump to: navigation, search

In economics, convex preferences is a property of an individual's ordering of various outcomes which roughly corresponds to the idea that "averages are better than the extremes". The concept roughly corresponds to the concept of diminishing marginal utility without requiring utility functions.

Notation

Comparable to the greater-than-or-equal-to ordering relation \geq for real numbers, the notation \succeq below can be translated as: 'is at least as good as' (in preference satisfaction).

Similarly, \succ can be translated as 'is strictly better than' (in preference satisfaction), and Similarly, \sim can be translated as 'is equivalent to' (in preference satisfaction).

Definition

Use x, y, and z to denote three consumption bundles (combinations of various quantities of various goods). Formally, a preference relation \succeq on the consumption set X is called convex if for any

x, y, z \in X where y \succeq x and z \succeq x ,

and for every \theta\in[0,1]:

\theta y + (1-\theta) z \succeq x .

i.e, for any two bundles that are each viewed as being at least as good as a third bundle, a weighted average of the two bundles is viewed as being at least as good than the third bundle.

A preference relation \succeq is called strictly convex if for any

x, y, z \in X where y \succeq x , z \succeq x , and  y \neq z,

and for every \theta\in(0,1):

\theta y + (1-\theta) z \succ x

i.e, for any two distinct bundles that are each viewed as being at least as good as a third bundle, a weighted average of the two bundles (including a positive amount of each bundle) is viewed as being strictly better than the third bundle.[1][2]

Alternative definition

Use x and y to denote two consumption bundles. A preference relation \succeq is called convex if for any

x, y \in X where y \succeq x

and for every \theta\in[0,1]:

\theta y + (1-\theta) x \succeq x .

That is, if a bundle y is preferred over a bundle x, then any mix of y with x is still preferred over x. [3]

A preference relation is called strictly convex if for any

x, y \in X where y \sim x

and for every \theta\in[0,1]:

\theta y + (1-\theta) x \succ x .
\theta y + (1-\theta) x \succ y .

That is, for any two bundles that are viewed as being equivalent, a weighted average of the two bundles is better than each of these bundles.[4]

Examples

1. If there is only a single commodity type, then any weakly-monotonically-increasing preference relation is convex. This is because, if y \geq x , then every weighted average of y and ס is also \geq x .

2. Consider an economy with two commodity types, 1 and 2. Consider a preference relation represented by the following Leontief utility function:

u(x_1,x_2) = \min(x_1,x_2)

This preference relation is convex. PROOF: suppose x and y are two equivalent bundles, i.e. \min(x_1,x_2) = \min(y_1,y_2). If the minimum-quantity commodity in both bundles is the same (e.g. commodity 1), then this imples x_1=y_1 \leq x_2,y_2. Then, any weighted average also has the same amount of commodity 1, so any weighted average is equivalent to x and y. If the minimum commodity in each bundle is different (e.g. x_1\leq x_2 but y_1\geq y_2), then this implies x_1=y_2 \leq x_2,y_1. Then \theta x_1 + (1-\theta) y_1 \geq x_1 and \theta x_2 + (1-\theta) y_2 \geq y_2, so \theta x + (1-\theta) y \succeq x,y. This preference relation is convex, but not strictly-convex.

3. A preference relation represented by linear utility functions is convex, but not strictly convex. Whenever x\sim y, every convex combination of x,y is equivalent to any of them.

4. Consider a preference relation represented by:

u(x_1,x_2) = \max(x_1,x_2)

This preference relation is not convex. PROOF: let x=(3,5) and y=(5,3). Then x\sim y since both have utility 5. However, the convex combination 0.5 x + 0.5 y = (4,4) is worse than both of them since its utility is 4.

Relation to indifference curves and utility functions

A set of convex-shaped indifference curves displays convex preferences: Given a convex indifference curve containing the set of all bundles (of two or more goods) that are all viewed as equally desired, the set of all goods bundles that are viewed as being at least as desired as those on the indifference curve is a convex set.

Convex preferences with their associated convex indifference mapping arise from quasi-concave utility functions, although these are not necessary for the analysis of preferences.

References

  1. Hal R. Varian; Intermediate Microeconomics A Modern Approach. New York: W. W. Norton & Company. ISBN 0-393-92702-4
  2. Mas-Colell, Andreu; Whinston, Michael; & Green, Jerry (1995). Microeconomic Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-507340-9
  3. Simon Board. "Preferences and Utility
  4. Nicholas J. Sanders, "Preference and Utility - Basic Review and Examples".

See also