Gyula Kőnig

From Infogalactic: the planetary knowledge core
(Redirected from Gyula König)
Jump to: navigation, search
Gyula Kőnig
200px
Born (1849-12-16)16 December 1849
Győr, Kingdom of Hungary
Died Script error: The function "death_date_and_age" does not exist.
Budapest, Kingdom of Hungary
Nationality Hungarian
Fields Mathematics
Alma mater University of Heidelberg
Doctoral advisor Leo Königsberger

Gyula Kőnig (16 December 1849 – 8 April 1913) was a Hungarian mathematician. His mathematical publications in foreign languages appeared under the name Julius König. His son Dénes Kőnig was a graph theorist.

Biography

Kőnig's name in Hungarian was Kőnig Gyula or in the more common European name order Gyula Kőnig, but when Kőnig contributed to German mathematical journals he called himself "Julius König."

Gyula Kőnig was active literarily and mathematically. He studied medicine in Vienna and, from 1868 on, in Heidelberg. After having worked, instructed by Hermann von Helmholtz, on electrical stimulation of nerves, he switched to mathematics and obtained his doctorate under the supervision of Leo Königsberger, a mathematician at that time. His thesis Zur Theorie der Modulargleichungen der elliptischen Functionen covers 24 pages. As a post-doc he completed his mathematical studies in Berlin attending lessons by Leopold Kronecker and Karl Weierstraß. He then returned to Budapest where he was appointed as a dozent at the University in 1871. He became a professor at the Teacher's College in Budapest in 1873 and, in the following year, was appointed professor at the Technical University of Budapest. He remained with the university for the rest of his life. He was on three occasions Dean of the Engineering Faculty and also on three occasions was Rector of the University. In 1889 he was elected a member of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences. In 1905 he retired but continued to give lessons on topics of his interest. His son Dénes also became a distinguished mathematician.

Works

Kőnig worked in many mathematical fields. His work on polynomial ideals, discriminants and elimination theory can be considered as a link between Leopold Kronecker and David Hilbert as well as Emmy Noether. Later on his ideas were simplified considerably, to the extent that today they are only of historical interest.

Kőnig already considered material influences on scientific thinking and the mechanisms which stand behind thinking.

<templatestyles src="Template:Blockquote/styles.css" />

The foundations of set theory are a formalization and legalization of facts which are taken from the internal view of our consciousness, such that our "scientific thinking" itself is an object of scientific thinking.

But mainly he is remembered for his contributions to and his opposition against set theory.

Kőnig and set theory

One of the greatest achievements of Georg Cantor was the construction of a one-to-one correspondence between the points of a square and the points of one of its edges by means of continued fractions. Kőnig found a simple method involving decimal numbers which had escaped Cantor.

In 1904, at the third International Congress of Mathematicians at Heidelberg, Kőnig gave a talk to disprove Cantor's continuum hypothesis. The announcement was a sensation and was widely reported by the press. All section meetings were cancelled so that everyone could hear his contribution.

Kőnig applied a theorem proved in the thesis of Felix Bernstein; this theorem, however, was not as generally valid as Bernstein had claimed. Ernst Zermelo, the later editor of Cantor's collected works, found the error already the next day. In 1905 there appeared short notes by Bernstein, correcting his theorem, and Kőnig, withdrawing his claim.

Nevertheless Kőnig continued his efforts to disprove parts of set theory. In 1905 he published a paper proving that not all sets could be well-ordered.

<templatestyles src="Template:Blockquote/styles.css" />

It is easy to show that the finitely defined elements of the continuum form a subset the continuum of cardinality \aleph_0. The reason is that such a definition must be given completely by a finite number of letters and punctuation marks, only a finite number of which is available.

This statement was doubted by Cantor in a letter to Hilbert in 1906:

<templatestyles src="Template:Blockquote/styles.css" />

Infinite definitions (which are not possible in finite time) are absurdities. If Kőnig's claim concerning the cardinality \aleph_0 of all finitely definable real numbers was correct, it would imply that the whole continuum of real numbers was countable; this is most certainly wrong. Therefore Kőnig's assumption must be in error. Am I wrong or am I right?[1]

Cantor was wrong. Today Kőnig's assumption is generally accepted. Contrary to Cantor, presently the majority of mathematicians considers undefinable numbers not as absurdities. This assumption leads, according to Kőnig,

<templatestyles src="Template:Blockquote/styles.css" />

in a strangely simple way to the result that the continuum cannot get well-ordered. If we imagine the elements of the continuum as a well-ordered set, those elements which cannot be finitely defined form a subset of that well-ordered set which certainly contains elements of the continuum. Hence in this well-order there should be a first not finitely definable element, following upon all finitely definable numbers. This is impossible. This number has just been finitely defined by the last sentence. The assumption that the continuum could be well-ordered has led to a contradiction.

Kőnig's conclusion is not stringent. His argument does not rule out the possibility that the continuum can be well-ordered; rather, it rules out the conjunction of "the continuum can be well-ordered by a definition in language L" and "the property of being definable in language L is itself definable in language L". The latter is no longer generally held to be true. For an explanation compare Richard's paradox.

The last part of his life Kőnig spent working on his own approach to set theory, logic and arithmetic, which was published in 1914, one year after his death. When he died he had been working on the final chapter of the book.

About Kőnig

At first Georg Cantor highly esteemed Kőnig. In a letter to Philip Jourdain in 1905 he wrote:

<templatestyles src="Template:Blockquote/styles.css" />

You certainly heard that Mr. Julius Kőnig of Budapest was lead astray, by a theorem of Mr. Bernstein which in general is wrong, to give a talk at Heidelberg, on the international congress of mathematicians, opposing my theorem according to which every set, i.e., every consistent multitude can be assigned an aleph. Anyway, the positive contributions from Kőnig himself are well done.

Later on Cantor changed his attitude:

<templatestyles src="Template:Blockquote/styles.css" />

What Kronecker and his pupils as well as Gordan have said against set theory, what Kőnig, Poincaré, and Borel have written against it, soon will be recognized by all as a rubbish.

— Letter to Hilbert, 1912

<templatestyles src="Template:Blockquote/styles.css" />

Then it will show up that Poincaré's and Kőnig's attacks against set theory are nonsense.

— Letter to Schwarz, 1913

Some papers and books by Kőnig

Literature and links

  • Brockhaus: Die Enzyklopädie, 20th ed. vol. 12, Leipzig 1996, p. 148.
  • W. Burau: Dictionary of Scientific Biography vol. 7, New York 1973, p. 444.
  • H. Meschkowski, W. Nilson (eds.): Georg Cantor Briefe, Berlin 1991.
  • W. Mückenheim: Die Mathematik des Unendlichen, Aachen 2006.
  • B. Szénássy, History of Mathematics in Hungary until the 20th Century, Berlin 1992.
  • Lua error in package.lua at line 80: module 'strict' not found..
  • Niedersächsische Staats- und Universitätsbibliothek Göttingen, Digitalisierungszentrum,[2][3]
  • Universitätsbibliothek Heidelberg[4]
  • The Mathematics Genealogy Project[5]

Notes

Lua error in package.lua at line 80: module 'strict' not found.

  1. Original in Cantor, ed. Herbert Meschkowski und Winfried Nilson, Briefe Berlin: Springer (1991).
  2. Göttinger Digitalisierungszentrum: Schnellsuche at dz-srv1.sub.uni-goettingen.de
  3. Göttinger Digitalisierungszentrum / Julius Koenig at www.ub.uni-heidelberg.de
  4. Julius Koenig at www.ub.uni-heidelberg.de
  5. http://genealogy.mathematik.uni-bielefeld.de/html/id.phtml?id=76335